Philosophy Phriday: Giraffes Are Taller Than Ants

The Daily Ant hosts a weekly series, Philosophy Phridays, in which real philosophers share their thoughts at the intersection of ants and philosophy. This is the eleventh contribution in the series, submitted by Dr. David Detmer.


Giraffes Are Taller Than Ants, and Other Observations

Giraffes are taller than ants. I claim to know this. Moreover, I maintain that “giraffes are taller than ants” is an objective truth. It accurately reports on one aspect of what the world, quite apart from human subjectivity, is really like, so that anyone who denies it–anyone who thinks that ants are as tall as, or taller than, giraffes–is simply mistaken, wrong, incorrect.

Giraffe
Geoff the Giraffe considers objective truths

But some philosophers, and quite a few other scholars in the humanities and social sciences, claim that we can’t know anything about what the world is really like. According to these thinkers, the problem is that we are all hopelessly finite and thoroughly conditioned beings who can’t help but perceive the world through the distorted lens of our own subjectivity, and can’t help but think about it only by means of the limited conceptual framework available to us. As a result, according to this view, we can never be justifiably confident that we are seeing an object as it really is, and understanding it accordingly; rather, for all we know, it could be that many important aspects of the object must remain utterly inaccessible to us, due to our perceptual and cognitive limitations, while other aspects are available to us only in a highly impure way, having been twisted and deformed by the biases and prejudices that we impose on the object from the outset. While some of these biases and prejudices may vary from person to person, depending on each individual’s unique genetic makeup and/or particular life experiences, others may be shared with other people who have undergone the same or similar conditioning. Thus, on this view, when people tend to agree about some matter, it may well be that this is not because they have accurately grasped the external object in its full independent objectivity, but rather because those who share this agreement have been subjected to the same or similar conditioning, whether social, political, economic, or educational, or based on gender, race, ethnicity, age, income, or some other set of contingencies. In short, according to this way of thinking, we are trapped within a kind of subjective predicament. We cannot see reality as it is, but rather only as it looks to us, where that, in turn, has been shaped and molded by forces outside of our control.

GiraffeJail
Geoff the Giraffe trapped in a prison of his own subjectivity

What can be done about this? Some have suggested that we give up on the project of trying to figure out what things are really like, and what the “objective” truth is. Instead, we might be content merely to strive for consensus within our group or culture (however that might be understood), and to call “true” whatever our group agrees is true. This is the ethnocentric approach, in which truth is defined in terms of consensus. Or, we might limit our inquiry to the question of which beliefs help us to cope with life successfully, and to call “true” whatever beliefs turn out to be helpful. This is the pragmatic approach, in which truth is defined in terms of utility.

What are we to make of these proposals? Some of the premises underlying them seem plausible enough. It would appear to be true that we can’t somehow jump outside of our subjective skins in order bump up against reality-as-it-is-in-itself. And it is a truism that people from different walks of life tend to view the world differently from one another.

Giraffe2
Geoff the Giraffe doesn’t view the world like Giselle

But it is also clear that this line of thought, if stretched too far, starts to undermine itself. If we don’t know what reality is like, how things stand, what the objective truth is, then we can’t possibly know that we don’t know what reality is like, how things stand, what the objective truth is. If one insists that all beliefs are merely subjective opinions that reflect the social conditioning of the believer, then this belief itself must be seen as merely a subjective opinion that reflects the social conditioning of the person who believes it. It is inconsistent to claim as an objective truth that there is no objective truth, or to claim to know that the true nature of things is such that we can never know the true nature of things.

This criticism is an ancient one, and is usually stated in the abstract. But let’s look at it concretely in connection with the proposal, mentioned above, that we should abandon the quest for objective truth, which is said to be unavailable to us in principle, and instead seek only what is allegedly more accessible to us–consensus or utility.

On the ethnocentric approach, to determine whether or not it is true that giraffes are taller than ants we would have to find out whether or not people in our culture think that giraffes are taller than ants. So we would need to investigate, not giraffes and ants, but rather people’s beliefs about them.

GiraffeGeoffJr
Geoff the Giraffe contemplates the mind of Geoff Jr.

But now notice this. Suppose we determine that there is indeed a consensus opinion on this issue in our culture: everyone agrees that giraffes are taller than ants. What is the status of this discovery? Have we uncovered an objective fact about some aspect of the world–namely, that it is really true that everyone in our culture thinks that giraffes are taller than ants (so that anyone who thought otherwise would be mistaken)? If so, we have now abandoned the premise that set us on this path in the first place–that objective truths of this sort are not available to us. To retain that premise, and to proceed in a manner consistent with our new ethnocentric approach, we would have to construe our new truth claim (that everyone in our culture agrees that giraffes are taller than ants) as itself established (as all truth claims are) by consensus. Thus, not only does “giraffes are taller than ants” mean ” everyone in our culture agrees that giraffes are taller than ants,” but this, in turn, must also be taken to mean that “everyone in our culture agrees that everyone in our culture agrees that giraffes are taller than ants.” And this would then have to mean that everyone agrees that everyone agrees that everyone agrees…and we’re off on an infinite regress.

Geoff3
Geoff the Giraffe: Where does he begin, and where does he end?

Another possibility would be to give up the claim that all objective truths are inaccessible to us, so that, while we can’t know whether or not giraffes are really (objectively) taller than ants, we can know what people really (objectively) think about this. But that claim is implausible. It is often difficult to know what people think. We can’t read minds, and thus have to draw inferences about people’s beliefs based on what they say and do. Moreover, if the culture is large enough it may be impossible to survey or otherwise study everyone in it, so that any conclusions about what everyone thinks would have to be based on generalizing from a sample. It is difficult to see on what basis anyone might think that knowledge claims based on such inferences and generalizations, which take as their subject matter something not directly accessible to us (other people’s thoughts), would somehow be more secure, more certain, less fallible, better candidates for the status of knowledge, than would be knowledge claims about the relative size of giraffes and ants based simply on looking at them. To put the point another way, if our subjective predicament closes us off from achieving knowledge about giraffes and ants, then so does it close us off from achieving knowledge about what people think. No practical problem facing someone trying to determine the relative heights of giraffes and ants is solved by shifting from the project of investigating giraffes and ants directly to that of investigating what people think about them.

TrapjawAnt
Anton the Ant, poised to capture an Objective Truth. Photo: Alex Wild

And exactly the same set of problems confronts the pragmatic alternative. On this view, “giraffes are taller than ants” means, “it is useful to believe that giraffes are taller than ants.” If this is taken as an objective truth, we contradict the premise driving the shift to a pragmatic approach. But if we maintain the pragmatic approach consistently we get an infinite regress: “Giraffes are taller than ants” means “it is useful to believe that giraffes are taller than ants,” which, in turn, means “it is useful to believe that it is useful to believe that giraffes are taller than ants,” and so on. And, from a practical point of view, what problem would be solved by this shift? It is often difficult to determine what will be the practical advantages and disadvantages of holding certain beliefs. More to the point, it would appear to be much more difficult than it would be to determine whether giraffes are taller than ants.

Some might object that arguments of this sort only work in connection with straightforwardly empirical and quantitative issues, such as determining whether or not giraffes are taller than ants. But perhaps they help to establish some subtler, philosophical, non-empirical issues as well, such as whether there is any practical advantage in abandoning the quest for objective truth in favor of an ethnocentric or pragmatic alternative.


DavidDetmerDr. David Detmer is a professor of philosophy at Purdue University Northwest. His upcoming book, Zinnophobia: The Battle Over History in Education, Politics, and Scholarship, will be published later this year or early next year by Zero Books. It is a defense of the work of radical historian Howard Zinn against his many critics. He is also the author of Freedom as a Value, Challenging Postmodernism: Philosophy and the Politics of Truth, Sartre Explained, and Phenomenology Explained.

5 thoughts on “Philosophy Phriday: Giraffes Are Taller Than Ants

Add yours

  1. The discussion of pragmatism is so shallow and inaccurate that it shouldn’t have been included. For the pragmatist, a belief is a habit. So the content of “giraffes are taller than ants” is cashed out in terms of its consequences in action. This analysis of meaning is the essential feature of pragmatism. Plenty of pragmatists – e.g. Rorty – and pretty-much-pragmatists – e.g. Ramsey, Wittgenstein – don’t think there’s anything interesting to be said about truth.

    Like

    1. In response to “Benji,” I would like to make two points. First it is a misreading of the relevant section of my brief essay to construe it as a discussion of “pragmatism” broadly or generally. Still less does this discussion address the differences on issues of meaning and truth dividing the various thinkers (Peirce, James, Dewey, Schiller, Rorty, Putnam, and so forth) who have called themselves “pragmatists.” Instead, I define my topic, much more precisely, as the proposal “to call ‘true’ whatever beliefs turn out to be helpful,” so that “truth is defined in terms of utility.” Benji’s objection amounts to the claim that I have misnamed my target—I should not have called the proposal that I criticize “the pragmatic approach.” But notice that this objection does not address the merits of my criticism of the proposal in question, whatever one thinks it should be called. There certainly are people who endorse the idea that truth should be defined in terms of utility, and my concern in the relevant section of this essay is to consider the cogency of that idea.
      Well, then, who are the people who endorse what I call “the pragmatic approach”? William James is one (all quotations drawn from his Pragmatism: A New Name for some Old Ways of Thinking):

      “The true is the name of whatever proves itself to be good in the way of belief.”

      “‘The true’, to put it very briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking, just as ‘the right’ is only the expedient in the way of our behaving.”

      “Ideas…become true just in so far as they help us to get into satisfactory relations with other parts of our experience.”

      Richard Rorty is another. He endorses “the idea that the beliefs we call ‘true’ are the ones we find most useful…” (“Intellectual Historians and Pragmatist Philosophy,” in John Pettegrew, ed., A Pragmatist’s Progress? Richard Rorty and American Intellectual History [Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, 2000], p. 208), says of his philosophy that its “whole point…is to stop distinguishing between the usefulness of a way of talking and its truth” (“Something to Steer by,” London Review of Books [June 20, 1996], p. 7), and states that “[c]alling something true is a way of commending our latest device for making ourselves happier” (“Rorty v. Searle, At Last: A Debate,” Logos Vol. 2, No. 3 [Summer 1999], p. 62). Indeed, while not every pragmatist endorses such an instrumentalist conception of truth, it appears to be true, not only that just about everybody who does endorse it is a pragmatist, but also (and this is my second point) that such a conception of truth is widely taken to be the distinguishing mark of pragmatism, or at least of some important form of pragmatism. Accordingly, Simon Blackburn, in The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, defines “pragmatic theory of truth” as “the view, especially associated with James, that the truth of a statement can be defined in terms of the utility of accepting it”; Bradley Dowden and Norman Swartz, in the entry on “Truth” in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, state that “A Pragmatic Theory of Truth holds (roughly) that a proposition is true if it is useful to believe”; and Richard L. Kirkham, in the essay “Truth, pragmatic theory of,” in the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, says that one of the two theories so designated holds that “a proposition counts as true if and only if behaviour based on a belief in the proposition leads, in the long run and all things considered, to beneficial results for the believers.” Perhaps this helps explain why I used the phrase “the pragmatic approach” to refer to the proposal “to call ‘true’ whatever beliefs turn out to be helpful,” so that “truth is defined in terms of utility.” In any case, the cogency of my critique of that proposal should be assessed on its merits, rather than on the basis of the name I have given to the proposal.

      Liked by 2 people

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

w

Connecting to %s

Powered by WordPress.com.

Up ↑

%d bloggers like this: